Continuing
from my previous blog, here I will explain some of what I have found out thus
far in my research about the science of consciousness in general and how it
applies to the possibility of foetuses having a type of consciousness.
What
I find remarkable about Shepherd mentioning foetal consciousness back in the
early 19th century, is that science today still doesn’t have a good
grasp of what consciousness is, and even less so when it comes to foetuses. In
the New Scientist published as recently as the 13th May 2017, Homes
states that “We don’t even fully understand what consciousness is” and that the
question of how it evolved and “what is it for?” has “Until recently, …. been
largely ignored”1. So I think it is all the more fascinating that
Shepherd doesn’t ignore the possibility of foetal consciousness back in the 19th
century2. Homes3 tells us the latest shift of focus in
science of consciousness is that scientific researchers have broadened their
focus now by analysing the historical evolution of consciousness, including
consciousness in animals, rather than restricting the question to what it is
and applying it only to humans, and thereby furthering our knowledge of the
“nature of consciousness” by approaching it from a different but related
research question.
Homes4
outlines the differing, competing theories and accounts of consciousness which
take this different research angle. There is still no one agreed scientific
view on it and much ignorance in this field remains5. The important
key concepts in this article by Homes which relate to my focus in this blog
post are that there are various “kinds of consciousness”6. This
means two things. One, that there may be different types of consciousness other
than the ones we are familiar with as human beings7. Two, that there
may be different levels of consciousness, ranging from “minimal consciousness”
to more complex ways of being conscious8. Homes wonderfully sums up
this message at the end of his article when he says “consciousness is not clear
cut” and that, by looking at the animal world, we appreciate what the
neuroscientist Anil Seth means when he says “there is not just one single way
of being conscious”9.
This,
I think, matches up well with Shepherd’s hypothesis that consciousness can be
simple early on in life, then be more complex when we are adults before
returning to a simple kind of consciousness after death. So I wonder whether what
Shepherd had in mind when writing about consciousness, including “consciousnesses
(simple or complex)”10, and “mental capacity” being “simple”11
is something akin to what we would now term minimal consciousness.
However,
there can be a fine line in determining the difference between very minimal
levels of consciousness and unconsciousness and this difference is not always
clearly understood. Block12, in his entry on ‘consciousness’ in ‘A
Companion to the Philosophy of Mind’ highlights that the philosopher Searle
puts forward and explores “petit mal epilepsy”13 as described by
Penfield. I shall put aside the criticisms and rebuttals of Searle’s approach
to consciousness and instead try to bring out how this type of epilepsy really
illustrates the difficulty of untangling different types of human conscious and
how to accurately delineate between consciousness and unconsciousness. Penfield
observed that his patients with petit mal epilepsy were able to do things like
walk around busy streets, drive a car and play a musical instrument despite
being described as “totally unconscious”.14 This raises two points.
One, as Block highlights, that this may be because, while they lack some types
of consciousness, such as “phenomenal
consciousness”, they still possess others, such as “cognitive and functional
consciousness”15. Two, Block questions the phrase “totally unconscious”
in an earlier work of Searles’ and explores the idea of whether what is really
going on is related to attentiveness16. On this picture, when we say
sufferers are unconscious yet managing to be up and about and navigating their
way through the world, it is more akin to being conscious but “on automatic
pilot” rather than actually being completely unconscious17. Not only
does this impact on how we want to demarcate and define the difference between
consciousness and unconsciousness, but it also has implications for how we talk
about different kinds of consciousness.18
The
relevance of the similarities and differences between conscious states and
unconscious states is that some scientists / paediatricians maintain that
foetal consciousness is a type of unconsciousness and that foetuses are in a
sleep-like state until birth19. This claim, I think, is of
particular interest when assessing how close Shepherd’s suggested hypotheses
are to contemporary scientific knowledge because in a different section in her
1827 treatise she calls sleep an unconscious state20.
So
how should we draw on all this when examining the concept of foetal
consciousness in Shepherd? At first glance, it might seem that foetuses are not
strictly speaking conscious, but rather, unconscious. However, considering that
this unconsciousness is likened to a sleep-like state and that people can
sleepwalk and petit mal epilepsy sufferers have sometimes been considered
unconscious despite being up and about and capable of doing tasks, should we
think of foetal unconsciousness as a type of very minimal consciousness, akin
to sleep and certain types of so-called unconscious behaviours? Are foetuses
unconscious in some ways but not others, making them seem unconscious? Would
Shepherd have refined her terms of simple consciousness and unconsciousness in
relation to foetuses had she known they may be in a sleep-like state? How
should we accurately interpret Shepherd’s notion of foetal consciousness and
how she meant it? How should we assess and compare it to the deeper knowledge
we now possess in philosophy and science about levels and types of
consciousness? These are some of the research questions I’m asking myself about
Lady Mary Shepherd and sharing with you to enjoy thinking about too.
1Homes, B., ‘Why Be Conscious?’ (cover story), 13th
May 2017, p29
2Shepherd, M. (1827) Essays on the Perception of an
External Universe and Other Subjects Connected
with
the Doctrine of Causation (first edition ed.). Piccadilly, London, London,
United Kingdom: John Hatchard and Son.
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt
3Homes, B., ‘Why Be Conscious?’ (cover story), 13th May
2017, p29
4Homes, B., ‘Why Be Conscious?’ (cover story), 13th May
2017, p29-31
5ibid
6ibid p31
7ibid p29-31
8ibid p31
9ibid p31
10 Quote from: “What then remains as given data? Nothing but
our sensations, mental consciousnesses, (simple or complex,) arbitrarily named,
and their relations” in Shepherd, M. “Essay II Upon the Nature of
the Five Organs of Sense, and their Manner of Action with Regard to External
Perception” p221 in (1827) Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and
Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (first edition
ed.). Piccadilly, London, London, United Kingdom: John Hatchard and Son.
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt
11 Quote from: “But the inquiry should be, whether when the
organs which are in relation to any individual capacity, undergo the change
called death, if the continuing mental capacity become simple in its aptitudes
again, or, whether it remain so far in an altered state by what it has gone
through in the present life, that it continues as the result of that
modification?” in Shepherd, M. “Essay X, The Reason Why We Cannot Conceive of Sensation
as Existing Necessarily, and Continuously by Itself” p379 in (1827) Essays on
the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine
of Causation (first edition ed.). Piccadilly, London, London, United Kingdom:
John Hatchard and Son.
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt)
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt)
In
other words, Shepherd (1827) thinks that either our mental capabilities go from
being simple to more complex in adulthood before becoming simple again after
death or that our mental capabilities continually change in some way
throughout.
12 Block, N., (2004) ‘Consciousness’ entry in ‘A companion
to the Philosophy of Mind’ ed, Guttenplan, S., Backwell companions to Philosophy,
Blackwell Publishing pp210-219
13ibid p217
14ibid
15ibid
16ibid p218
17ibid
18ibid. In addition, Block (2004, p218) argues that “The
main error here is to transfer by conflation an obvious function of
access-consciousness to phenomenal consciousness”. For an overview and explanation
of these terms see http://protoscience.wikia.com/wiki/Phenomenal_and_Access_Conciousness
This
terminology also shows that there are even different terms for various levels
and types of consciousness between philosophy and science.
19 p255 in Lagercrantz, H., and Changeux, Jean-Pierre, (2009)
‘The Emergence of Human Consciousness: From Foetal to Neonatal Life’, Pediatric
research, 65 (3), p255-60
20 from quote where Shepherd uses sleep as an example of an
unconscious state: “when unconscious, (as in sound sleep)…” in Shepherd,
M., Chapter VII “Application of the Doctrine Contained
in the Preceding Essay to the Evidence of our Belief in Several Opinions.” p155
in (1827) Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects
Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (first edition ed.). Piccadilly,
London, London, United Kingdom: John Hatchard and Son.
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt
Available at: https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/essaysonpercepti00shep_djvu.txt
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.