Tuesday 23 January 2018

Shepherd vol 1 ebook chapter 2: Analytic and Scientific Features in Shepherd’s Philosophy


Chapter 2: Analytic and Scientific Features in Shepherd’s Philosophy 

There are various different approaches to doing analytic philosophy, all of them valuable in their own way. In this chapter, I shall explore some features of analytic philosophy and how it relates to science. I will show how I think this sheds light on how to read Shepherd’s writings, without imposing my own methodological preferences onto her system of thought.

Lamarque and Olsen list features of analytic philosophy’s methodology[i]:

·         “the prominent application of logic and conceptual analysis;

·         the commitment to rational methods of argument;

·         the emphasis on objectivity and truth;

·         the predilection for spare, literal prose, eschewing overly rhetorical or figurative language;

·         the felt need to define terms and offer explicit formulation of thesis;

·         the quasi-scientific dialectical method of hypothesis/counter-example/modification;

·         the tendency to tackle narrowly defined problems, often working within on-going debates”

They also list optional “presuppositions” alongside this[ii]:

·         “the treatment of scientific progress as paradigmatic;

·         a tendency towards ontological “parsimony”, realism about science, and physicalism about mind;

·         the belief that philosophical problems are in some sense timeless or universal, at least not merely constructs of history and culture.”

A philosopher does not need to display all the above features to be considered an analytic philosopher. So, even if one only agreed that a few of these features were in her works, she could still be classified as an analytic philosopher. However, I think all of the above features can be found in Shepherd’s writing, except that she is not a physicalist in her concept of mind. I argue that this such an incredibly high percentage of analytic features contained within her philosophy that the possibility of her being the first analytic philosopher should be seriously considered and possibly acknowledged in mainstream history of philosophy. To have so many of these features threaded throughout both of her two lengthy treatises is, I think, remarkable, especially considering that her philosophical works were published in the early part of the nineteenth century, and Frege, who is seen as the father of analytic philosophy, wasn’t even born until 1848.    

I maintain her arguments are in a style of analytic philosophy, a style which prioritizes being explicitly logically structured, ahistorical and not grounded in literary, cultural or theological concepts. As I shall explain in chapters 3 and 4, Shepherd is frequently examining the argument structure of other philosophers. She evaluates their arguments and definitions at length assessing how logically they are constructed. I also explain how she takes the time to clarify her own approach to analyzing concepts, definitions and framing her theses and arguments. I also give examples of how she makes explicit what rules of reasoning and logical methodology she advocates.

I argue that Shepherd’s authorial voice throughout both her treatises[iii],[iv] also suits this description of philosophizing. She does write very literally, plainly and technically without having a literary style to her argumentation. All her arguments come across as having a keen desire to be objective and reach the truth, no matter how apparently obscure the subject matter. She does not rely on historical or cultural reasons for her arguments but provides abstract metaphysical, logical and epistemological reasons for her claims which her readers, irrespective of their era, can appreciate in a timeless and universal sense. As I will explore in chapter 9, Shepherd is a Realist philosopher. However, I think one can expect her Realism to look a little different from the contemporary description of it above, given that she is mostly addressing seventeenth to early nineteenth century philosophy with only the general knowledge available to her at the time.

In addition, she displays other features which some analytic philosophers opt for, such as keeping to a tight focus, structure and debate within each of her treatises, as well as analyzing “features which are central and characteristic”[v] of her chosen philosophical problems. Her philosophical arguments are “slow, meticulous” and she aims to provide “strong arguments to support precise, clearly defined theses”[vi]. Shepherd also furthers philosophical discussion in accordance with the “familiar analytic mode” of putting forward her stance by comparing and contrasting her views with other philosophers, criticizing where necessary, so she thereby “enters into a dialogue with other contributors”[vii].

Furthermore, I think Shepherd’s style of analytic philosophy suits the technical metaphysics she wants to examine and makes her metaphysics stronger because she has kept scientific possibilities in mind when considering metaphysical possibility, as far as it was possible to do so in her era. Shepherd does use rules of argumentation described in logic and she mentions logical rules. This abstract, logical methodology, I suggest, crosses-over into resembling the logic of science. In this way, I suggest she makes use of a quasi-scientific dialectical methodology, although this is more varied than only relying on counter-examples as a way of adjusting a hypothesis. I think we also need to bear in mind that scientific dialectic in her era had a somewhat different style from that which is used these days. By and large, there were less strong demarcations between different disciplines and thinkers commonly took an interest in and wrote on a wide variety of disciples. So abstract thought in general, as well as areas in philosophy, logic and science were a lot more fluid than is common today and any given individual moved freely between topics as and when they felt it relevant. For instance, as I explored in the last chapter, Babbage was interested in the sciences and mathematics but this also led him to begin the foundations of computer science (before it became a science in itself) and to write about philosophy, including about miracles. As I mentioned in the previous chapter, Babbage was also fascinated with Astronomy and Shepherd enjoyed meeting friends from the Astronomical Society he helped set up.

So for the rest of this chapter, I shall explore how developments in contemporary astronomy can help us appreciate and value the analytical, logical, quasi-scientific methodology found in Shepherd’s writings. I aim to show that her analytic-logic of science methodology can somewhat link with the scientific method behind discoveries today, giving her contemporary relevance for many fields of study.  To do this, I shall narrow my focus to two of Shepherd’s analogies for the topic of the afterlife in her second treatise[viii], an aspect of her philosophy I expand on in part 3.

Classic, timeless concepts analysed in metaphysics, which fall under the subject matter of universals and particulars, include questions such as “On what grounds do we say that the butterfly that emerges from a cocoon is one and the same animal as the caterpillar that spun the cocoon?” and “are there some changes a person could undergo, after which what remains would no longer be a person?”[ix]. Shepherd raises this very question through her analogy of a bug on a leaf by pointing out how a “worm” sheds its outer layer which “wholly perishes” while the worm lives on as a seemingly different insect which can fly around in “boundless space”[x]. This explores the metaphysical topics of continuous existence and whether dying means we go out of existence or if we continue to exist in some way, for instance, in an afterlife and how this relates to personal identity, eternity and immortality.

Shepherd uses this analogy to serve many purposes. One purpose is to provide an intuitive counterexample to those who argue against the possibility of an afterlife on the basis that dispersion of particles entails death[xi]. As we saw earlier in this chapter, this is in line with analytic philosophy which makes use of counterexamples. A further purpose is a methodological one. This analogy illustrates the restrictions involved in being too empiricist. The empiricist can end up being like the bug on the leaf who, by reasoning from its restricted life experience to date, wrongly concludes it will die when it sheds its outer layer and will never know a life beyond what it experiences now. This demonstrates the advantages of Shepherd’s Rationalist, analytic approach of hypothesising rationally and logically beyond what experience has so-far confirmed. The bug would have discovered a theory closer to the truth had it used different methodological thinking. I maintain that this methodological style is more quasi-scientific than it first appears. There are many big questions still unanswered in science about what exists, not just in relation to life and death but what exists in our universe generally. This is where the logic of science comes into its own. There are times in science when it is more productive to logically move from hypothesis to observation to help us make a discovery.  

One such example[xii] is the Planet Nine theory which, I suggest, is akin to her bug on the leaf analogy. In 2016, a team of science researchers discovered empirical evidence which supported their hypothesis of why the sun tilts[xiii]. This means that they reasoned logically about how Planet Nine impacts on things around it in the solar system first rather than start with an empirical observation of the sun and Planet Nine[xiv]. This helped them make a discovery faster and more efficiently about something which is very difficult to observe. Indeed, here we see how scientific theory started with the concept of an hypothetical planet, called Planet Nine and then went about looking for empirical evidence to support the hypothesis[xv]. Empirical evidence did eventually support the existence of the hypothesised planet, although scientists have struggled to find the exact location of it. So similarly, Shepherd talks about the afterlife not as something to be empirically proven initially but to be logically and rationally explored first. So I think her example of a bug’s empirical experiences being restricted to its leaf, making it ignorant of the possibilities beyond what its senses discover, is relevant to situations in scientific discovery too. Had these scientists restricted their thinking to only directly observable phenomenon rather than working through various logical possibilities about the cosmos, they may never have hit upon the best explanation.

Shepherd’s approach to metaphysics and scientific method (of rationalising through a topic as far as our minds will go before expecting any empirical evidence to confirm it, as well as the usefulness of rough ideas for initially guiding us to the truth) is explicitly seen in the way Batygin describes the discovery process[xvi]. First there was reasoning about possibilities, resulting in more than one theory. This can be seen when Batygin states “I actually had theorized this in 2012 and wrote about it and the theory was almost exactly the same, except for it wasn’t Planet Nine doing the torqueing but a companion star.”[xvii] Shepherd[xviii] also provides more than one possible explanation, leaving open which may be closest to the truth about the afterlife. This open-mindedness is also useful in science where hypothetical theories try to resolve tensions about a phenomena. This can be seen when Batygin describes the puzzle of the tilting sun and the latest theory: “It does help us understand planet formation because planet formation theory dictates that all things must start out co-planar, in the same plane. The fact that the Sun is tilted with respect to the rest of the solar system is almost a violation of that very fundamental principle, so understanding what’s going on there is important.”[xix]

So, I think Shepherd outlines an analytic philosophical approach which suits scientific methodology and discovery. This is interesting because it would be easy to assume that an empiricist would match up with science better than a rationalist. However, as can be seen here, scientists often work from hypothesis to observation rather than invariably working the other way round. Hence, I think Shepherd’s logical and rational analysis of things that are not fully comprehended about the world and human life is not only fascinating within the history of philosophy but is a relevant approach for modern science today.    

Another recent scientific discovery which, I think, sheds light on Shepherd’s philosophical methodology, is supermassive black holes. Although it also applies to the bug on the leaf analogy, here I will focus on the compass analogy. 

In Shepherd’s analogy, the captain makes use of available equipment, in this case a compass, to track the orientation of the ship in relation to the location of north[xx]. This provides compass readings which we use to turn an inadequate (rough) idea of where north is into a geographical reality[xxi].

Planet 9 shows how ground-breaking scientific discoveries often consist of a bold, theoretical hypothesis based on meticulous rational reasoning and explanation which can be so accurate that it can be later proved with observation. This rationalistic approach also applies to the discovery that supermassive black holes can orbit each other after galaxies join up together[xxii]. Professor Taylor[xxiii], who was involved with the project, describes how the discovery took place and the role of theorizing:

“For a long time, we've been looking into space to try and find a pair of these supermassive black holes orbiting as a result of two galaxies merging.”[xxiv]

“Even though we've theorized that this should be happening, nobody had ever seen it until now."[xxv]

Similarly, the astronomers examined radio signal readings from radio telescopes to track the “trajectory” and orbiting motions of the supermassive black holes[xxvi]. This not only leads to more adequate (clear) ideas about how supermassive black holes orbit and why, but it could also provide us with possible knowledge of what our galaxy could be like in the future[xxvii]. So I think Shepherd is right to see her approach to the afterlife as rigorous enough to lead to good enough ideas for now which may be somewhat substantiated in the future and lead to refined adequate ideas about the afterlife.

Perhaps it is easier to see the value of such hypotheses these days, because recent technological progress has enabled us to better test seemingly far-fetched hypotheses to check if they correlate with observable reality. Taylor[xxviii] admits that technology has played an important role in providing sufficiently detailed data which provided the empirical evidence. Indeed, it was as recently as 2016 that researchers could provide empirical evidence to prove Einstein’s theory of the existence of gravitational waves, one hundred years after he hypothesised it[xxix]. Now our picture of gravitational waves and how the universe works is coming together between these two recent discoveries. From Einstein’s theory of gravitational waves a century ago, we are now gaining an understanding of how some types of black holes crash into each other and combine which, like stones thrown into water, give rise to a ripple effect through space-time, known as gravitational waves[xxx]. So I suggest this is perhaps what Shepherd was aiming for when she theorised possibilities about the afterlife, given she hopes to “throw light upon this subject, hitherto supposed to lie beyond the reach of human discovery” and wishes that “a scientific knowledge of its principles be obtained”[xxxi]. 







[i] Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen, eds., ‘General Introduction’, in ‘Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition: An Anthology’, Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies (Wiley-Blackwell, Blackwell Publishing, 2004), p2.
[ii] Lamarque and Olsen, p2.
[iii] Mary Shepherd, An Essay upon the Relation of Cause and Effect : Controverting the Doctrine of Mr. Hume, Concerning the Nature of That Relation, with Observations upon the Opinions of Dr. Brown and Mr. Lawrence Connected with the Same Subject (London, United Kingdom: Printed for T. Hookham, 1824), https://archive.org/stream/essayuponrelatio00shepiala#page/n7/mode/2up.
[iv] Mary Shepherd, Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (Piccadilly, London, United Kingdom: John hatchard and Son., 1827), https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/#page/n7/mode/2up.
[v] Lamarque and Olsen, ‘General Introduction’, p5.
[vi] Lamarque and Olsen, p5.
[vii] Lamarque and Olsen, p5.
[viii] Shepherd, Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation.
[ix] S. Gorovitz and R. G. Williams, Philosophical Analysis: An Introduction to Its Language & Techniques, 2nd edition (New York, USA: Random House, 1969), p136.
[x] Mary Shepherd, ‘Chapter VII. Application Of the Doctrine Contained In the Preceding Essay To the Evidence Of Our Belief In Several Opinions. Section III. Observations on the Essential Difference between Body and Mind.’, in Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (Piccadilly, London, United Kingdom: John hatchard and Son., 1827), p158-9, https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/#page/154/mode/2up.
[xi] Shepherd, p158.
[xii] Liba Kaucky, ‘Planet 9 and the Bug on the Leaf’, The Lady Mary Shepherd Salon (blog), 27 May 2017, https://theladymaryshepherdphilosophysalon.blogspot.co.uk/2017/05/planet-9-and-bug-on-leaf.html.
[xiii] S. Stirone, ‘Planet Nine May Be Responsible for Tilting the Sun: How Our Possible Rogue Planet May Be Messing with Our Solar System’, Astronomy Magazine, 19 October 2016, http://www.astronomy.com/news/2016/10/planet-nine-tilting-the-sun.
[xiv] Stirone.
[xv] Stirone.
[xvi] Stirone.
[xvii] Stirone.
[xviii] Shepherd, Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation.
[xix] Stirone, ‘Planet Nine May Be Responsible for Tilting the Sun: How Our Possible Rogue Planet May Be Messing with Our Solar System’.
[xx] Mary Shepherd, Chapter I. On Continuous Existence. (Piccadilly, London, United Kingdom: John hatchard and Son., 1827), p36, https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/#page/13/mode/1up.
[xxi] Shepherd, p36.
[xxii] Anon., ‘Groundbreaking Discovery Confirms Existence of Orbiting Supermassive Black Holes’, educational, EurekAlert: The global Source for Science News, 27 June 2017, https://www.eurekalert.org/pub_releases/2017-06/uonm-gdc062617.php.
[xxiii] Anon.,.
[xxiv] Anon.,.
[xxv] Anon.,.
[xxvi] Anon.,.
[xxvii] Anon.,.
[xxviii] Anon.,.
[xxix] Anon.,.
[xxx] Anon.,.
[xxxi] Mary Shepherd, ‘Essay VI, That Sensible Qualities Cannot Be Causes-against Mr. Hume.’, in Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (Piccadilly, London, United Kingdom: John hatchard and Son., 1827), p308, https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/#page/296/mode/1up/search/essay+VI.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.

Shepherd vol 2: Bibliography

 Bibliography: