Tuesday, 23 January 2018

Shepherd vol 1 ebook chapter 6 Shepherd's Counterarguments


Chapter 6: Shepherd’s Counterarguments 

In this chapter, I would like to explore a fresh perspective on Hume’s argument against miracles by analysing his claims in light of his fellow Scottish philosopher, Lady Mary Shepherd, who directly argues against his views in her essay VIII ‘That Human Testimony is of Sufficient Force to Establish the Credibility of Miracles’ in her second treatise ‘Perception of an External Universe, Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation’[i] (published 1827 but possibly written much earlier). As far as I am aware, philosophical literature has not yet specifically researched Shepherd’s counterarguments to Hume about miracles and how they affect the plausibility of Hume’s claims. 

Shepherd’s key counterarguments[ii] (in her essay VIII first published 1827) against Hume’s views (in EHU originally published 1748) on miracles identify and target specific potential flaws in his argument. One key counterargument Shepherd puts forward is that she thinks Hume has erroneously defined what a miracle is[iii]. At the heart of their disagreement lies their contrasting views on the laws of nature which, in addition to their different readings of scripture, impacts on their respective definitions of a miracle. Shepherd diverges from Hume’s various wordings of his definition of a miracle by offering her alternative definition of a miracle as “an exception to nature’s apparent course”[iv]. By substituting violation for exception and adding the word apparent, Shepherd has modified Hume’s definition in a significant way because this gives her an opening for arguing, contra Hume, that the existence of miracles is plausible and credible. One way Shepherd’s argument hits at Hume’s definition is that, as I have shown earlier, he justifies his definition on the basis that he has described miracles in accordance with how everyone thinks of miracles and how they are “denominated” in society (EHU 10 footnote 1; SBN 115). However, Shepherd questions that everyone does conceive of miracles in the way Hume describes and she maintains that his definition is at odds with scripture. This is for two reasons. First, Shepherd cites in a footnote that:

“The word miracle, in its derivation, signifies only a wonderful thing; that is, something at which we wonder, because contrary to our usual experience, or in other words, an interruption to that we conceive the course of nature.”[v]

In this way, the etymological root of the word miracle gives support to Shepherd’s redefinition which highlights that miracles only seem completely out of the ordinary because they go against the grain of our understanding of how nature functions, which we have gained through experience. So, our understanding of nature’s workings is only based on what we are able to gather from our senses and experience and so may not be a completely accurate reflection of all the intricacies of nature’s full capabilities. Thus, on Shepherd’s view, it is misleading of Hume to insist on a miracle involving a break with the laws of nature. As I discuss in the following chapter, I find Shepherd’s view here especially plausible because it concurs with several other Christian philosophers and theologians. 

Perhaps this is why Shepherd draws on another, related way to weaken Hume’s chosen definition, by citing that it does not cohere with the generally accepted view of how God acts in the world. She claims:

“…there is always understood to be a power in some superior influence in nature, in the presiding energy of an essential God, acting as an additional cause, equal to the alleged variety of effects.”[vi]

Much as she says she aims this remark at Hume’s phrase “violation of the laws of nature” (EHU 10.90; SBN 114), I think this criticism she makes has just as much if not greater force against Hume’s footnote (EHU 10 footnote 1; SBN 115) where he specifies God’s role within a miracle as being a “particular volition” which causes “a transgression of a law of nature”. In this way, Shepherd shows that Hume’s assumption, that when God is said to act in the world He breaks the laws of nature, need not be accepted at face value and could be rejected on religious, metaphysical grounds[vii]. This is important to Shepherd because she is keen to correct any misconceptions surrounding miracles which may turn readers of Hume’s essay away from the Christian faith. Shepherd notes that she would like to “examine” Hume’s account of miracles “which had sufficient attraction in it to draw the opinion of many from the belief of Christianity”[viii].

Furthermore, I think Shepherd could be showing that Hume’s definition may also frame the debate in a way that enables him to argue with more conviction than is actually warranted. Indeed, I suggest Hume’s preference for an interruption rather than an exception occurring within the cause of nature is problematic because it doesn’t take into account that naturally occurring events can surprise us. So, I think Shepherd is showing an awareness that we are more likely to hold erroneous beliefs about unusual events if there is a general denial of natural events being capable of exception. This can be seen when Shepherd writes:

“nature is so far from keeping up any constant analogy in her works, that the very aversion to believe in excepted cases to those of experience, arises from that puerile adherence to a customary association of thought, which made the Indian Prince a child rather than a philosopher who reasoned justly (according to Mr. Hume’s argument) when he refused to ‘believe the first relation of frost.’ ”[ix]   

In this passage, Shepherd shows that Hume undermines his own argument with his Indian Prince example because it could also be used to illustrate various weaknesses in his account.

One way the Indian Prince example shows up problems in Hume’s account is that it could be argued that his definition is a counterproductive way of thinking about miracles because it could lead people to react like the Indian Prince, which, as we have seen, Shepherd generally considers such an approach to be a “childish” model, unsuitable for philosophy[x]. This is because people would become accustomed to dismissing natural events that seem very astonishing, simply because they are completely out of their experience and give rise to wonder. Consequently, they would be more likely to disbelieve reports of such events altogether despite attempting to reason in a sound manner. Thus, this approach would be detrimental to gaining knowledge of the world and encourage ignorance, despite this being the opposite of Hume’s intentions. I suspect Hume doesn’t think he is leaving himself open to this possible objection because he takes the time to distinguish the freezing point phenomenon as “extraordinary” not “miraculous” because this event will consistently happen repeatedly under the same conditions (EHU 10.89, footnote 1; SBN 114). In this way, Hume could try to dismiss her objection by arguing that he is merely stating that the freezing point phenomenon encountered by the Indian Prince is only showing an instance of a natural event which is “not conformable to” (EHU 10.89; SBN 114) our experience (EHU 10.89 footnote 1; SBN 114). Hence, this type of natural event does not amount to an instance of something which is at odds with the laws of nature. On the contrary, what happens at freezing point is in fact an example of a law of nature. However, given that this argument relies on us assenting to Hume’s (EHU) definition of a miracle as being an interruption to the course of nature, I think Shepherd (1827) could still claim that Hume’s approach does not provide the best explanation because it creates an unnecessary suspicion of events that strike us as remarkable, as well as not fitting into the religious context of miracles. Shepherd instead resolves these tensions by incorporating God into the “one universal law” of nature by explaining His acts as constituting an additional cause to the causes and effects Hume focuses on[xi]. This has the advantage of slotting events outside of our experience cohesively into the overall picture of a mostly, but not invariably, uniform course of nature. In this way, Shepherd also wishes to demystify Hume’s talk of certain laws as constituting, on Hume’s view, “the ‘secret powers’ and capacities of bodies and minds; the mysterious influences of distinct mases of things, antecedent to their operation upon our senses” and “the mysterious storehouse of unperceived nature” which gives rise to “new un-seen events” which will “alter our experience in future”[xii].

I agree with Shepherd here that this undermines Hume’s attempt to provide a common sense, plausible account of the course of nature because anything that is harder to explain is unsatisfactorily relegated to the ambiguous and unpredictable category of strangely enigmatic events and laws. I would add that, by leaving space for the secretive and mysterious in nature, Hume may also be undermining his aim of combatting “all kinds of superstition and delusion” (EHU 10.86; SBN 110) because this kind of talk and way of thinking makes people more prone to forming superstitious habits and patterns of thought because it can give rise to fear, uncertainty and irrational thoughts about the course of nature and its impact on their lives. Given that this is in line with Hume’s general concerns about superstition, this may weaken Hume’s account of miracles because despite overtly removing a superstitious approach to nature, he is simultaneously leaving room for a superstitious brain-pattern to form around aspects of nature he can’t explain or may surprise us because it is the first time that a person has observed or heard of that natural event. Hume seems to implicitly refute the notion of God acting in the world given his rejection of miracles where God wills an event to happen. Nevertheless, I suggest that Hume is not intending to leave no room for God acting in the world in some way. This is because Hume mentions in passing that:

“…it is impossible for us to know the attributes or actions of such a Being, otherwise than from the experience we have of his productions, in the usual course of nature.” (EHU 10.99 SBN 129).         

A second way the Indian Prince example shows up problems in Hume’s account (EHU 10) is that it illustrates the flaws that can arise from a very empirical account of miracles which works from experience towards a conclusion. The example leads Shepherd to argue that Hume’s refutation of miracles includes the counterintuitive claim that nature can be affected or changed by experience. Shepherd cites and examines the part of Hume’s central doctrine about miracles which, according to her, makes the “false assertion”[xiii] that:

“…as a firm and unalterable experience has established these laws, the proof against a miracle, from the very nature of the fact, is as entire as any argument from experience can possibly be imagined.” (EHU 10.90; SBN 114).         

 Shepherd argues that our experiences of the external world cannot plausibly be claimed to be “created nor arranged” by sensory perception[xiv]. Shepherd is unconvinced that sensory experience can “measure” changes in the external world and states her view thus: “Our experience never established, nor can ever be the measure of the laws of nature” before further arguing that experience “never can be the measure of what alteration might take place under certain altered circumstances exterior to the senses”[xv]. This empirical feature of Hume’s account (EHU 10), illustrated by the Indian Prince, represents, for Shepherd, exactly where people go wrong and why she judges her definition of a miracle as an improvement on Hume’s. Shepherd maintains that, like the Prince, we make the error that:

“… we deem some limited observation we make, the measure of universal fact; we draw general conclusions from particular premises; until extended knowledge acquaints us with exceptions, and sometimes with single and most important exceptions to otherwise universal facts.”[xvi].

I think this passage in Shepherd is compelling because, unlike Hume, she is taking into account the problem of induction as illustrated by examples such as grue[xvii] or black swan problems[xviii] within the context of miracles. If our methodology for gaining knowledge of the external world is based on individual experience and observation then we may end up with more limited knowledge of universal facts, in much the same way that we are ignorant if we assume all emeralds are green simply because this is all we have been taught by others or have encountered for ourselves in the world[xix]. So I think Shepherd[xx] is right to claim that if there’s a narrow focus on and priority given to observable experience, then apparent anomalies to uniform experience cause unnecessary surprise and are more confusing than if we treat them as a normal part of experience that can be legitimately examined with as much rigour as occurrences which are in keeping with previously known laws of nature.

A related criticism Shepherd makes is that she suggests Hume is arguing inconsistently between his miracles essay and earlier in his Enquiry. Shepherd notices that Hume claims, amongst other things, that nature can “change her course without a contradiction”, that we are ignorant of nature’s ‘secret powers’, that sensory experience cannot always tell us about “those unperceived laws which truly govern the effect in every case” and that just because nature seems uniform, it cannot be assumed that this will remain the case in future[xxi]. If Shepherd has represented Hume’s argument earlier in his Enquiry fairly here, she has highlighted a direct contradiction in his views between his general philosophical principles and his refutation of miracles. Shepherd lists her main concerns with these two apparently contradictory passages as being that Hume has not consistently put forward an account of what an efficient cause is and that he therefore cannot “distinguish” his true and false propositions[xxii]. This is important because these propositions are used by Hume as premises leading to his conclusion that “custom is cause”[xxiii]. She then notes that he “suddenly turns the tables in the essay on miracles”[xxiv] by adding that only custom can be:

“cause, it alone can be the reason of our belief in testimony, and of our supposing there is any necessary connection between the custom of believing in testimony, and the reality of the events testified”[xxv].

Hence, Shepherd is not satisfied with the level of rigour in Hume’s argument and attempts to resolve this tension in her essay. I interpret Shepherd[xxvi] as implying that Hume has set up a ‘straw man fallacy’ in his essay on miracles in order to refute their existence more conclusively than is possible. In order to restore credibility to miracles, Shepherd reformulates Hume’s question of whether a break in the laws of nature is possible to the question of “whether an interruption to nature’s apparent course can take place?”[xxvii]. She then breaks this question down into the following three questions:

“First, whether the apparent course of nature can be altered?

Secondly, whether the evidence produced to prove such an alteration be credible?

Thirdly, if it be credible, in what manner the miracle itself becomes evidence of any particular doctrine”[xxviii]

In answer to the first question, Shepherd argues that the doctrine of efficient cause proves that exceptions to the apparent course of nature are possible and that there is evidence that unusual, “marvellous” events truly happen[xxix]. Shepherd then suggests that miracles should be seen as being on par with and equally worthy of analysis as other events which are also unusual but are believed to have an unknown adequate cause[xxx]. In answer to her second question, Shepherd responds by outlining her main criteria for testimony about “marvellous events” which focuses on whether the testifier had possible motives for making false claims and how much “confidence” was needed under the circumstances to tell the truth[xxxi]. This coheres with her earlier “axiom” concerning testimony which states that we place our trust in testimony which is not adversely affected by “any motive to falsehood” or “self-interest”[xxxii]. She builds on her notion of and criteria for believable testimony when answering her third question by arguing that, conversely, if the testimony does not involve some sort of risk to the testifier’s “self-interest” yet advocates a dogma then we should be more cautious about their testimony of that miracle[xxxiii]. Shepherd does not share Hume’s scepticism about how successfully we can detect false doctrines because she maintains that falsehoods will show up in the lack of quality of the evidence provided[xxxiv]. Nevertheless, she would not go on to advocate using miracles to settle minor disputes within the Catholic Church, possibly because she feels that this could descend into abusing miracles by using them as a means to win rows[xxxv]. Nevertheless, she does strongly conclude in her essay by supporting the testimony of the Apostles with her argument that they provided that testimony at the expense of their own interest and that she judges that it is more plausible that the Gospel contains truth than arguments that claim it does not[xxxvi].



[i] Mary Shepherd, ‘“Essay VIII: That Human Testimony Is Of Sufficient Force To Establish the Credibility Of Miracles.”’, in Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (Piccadilly, London, United Kingdom: John hatchard and Son., 1827), 325–45, https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/#page/n7/mode/2up.
[ii] Shepherd.
[iii] Shepherd.
[iv] Shepherd, p335.
[v] Shepherd, footnote p335.
[vi] Shepherd, ‘“Of Miracles”’, p329.
[vii] Shepherd, ‘“Of Miracles”’.
[viii] Shepherd, p330.
[ix] Shepherd, p328-9.
[x] Shepherd, 341.
[xi] Shepherd, p329.
[xii] Shepherd, p330-1.
[xiii] Shepherd, p330.
[xiv] Shepherd, p330-1.
[xv] Shepherd, p330-1.
[xvi] Shepherd, p332.
[xvii] Nelson Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, 2nd edition (Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA: Harvard UP, 1955).
[xviii] N. N. Taleb, The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable, 2nd edition (London, UK: Penguin Books, 2010).
[xix] Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast.
[xx] Shepherd, ‘“Of Miracles”’.
[xxi] Shepherd, p333-5.
[xxii] Shepherd, p333.
[xxiii] Shepherd, p333.
[xxiv] Shepherd, p333.
[xxv] Shepherd, p333-4.
[xxvi] Shepherd, ‘“Of Miracles”’.
[xxvii] Shepherd, p335.
[xxviii] Shepherd, p336.
[xxix] Shepherd, p336.
[xxx] Shepherd, p336.
[xxxi] Shepherd, p337.
[xxxii] Shepherd, p328.
[xxxiii] Shepherd, p337-40.
[xxxiv] Shepherd, p339.
[xxxv] Shepherd, p339.
[xxxvi] Shepherd, p345.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.

Shepherd vol 2 ebook: Bibliography

  Bibliography: Dictionary Scottish Architects | Part of Historic Environment Scotland. ‘25DSA Architect Biography Report in Dictionary of S...