Tuesday, 23 January 2018

Shepherd vol 1 ebook chapter 3 (Circularity and Begging the Question)


Chapter 3: Understanding the Analytic Approach to Circularity and Begging the Question

Shepherd mentions arguing in a circle and question begging in several places in her writings. First I shall examine what we commonly mean by circularity. 

There are many ways of trying to clarify what circularity is. All descriptions try to elucidate the notion that it is called circular because the structure of the thing in question, be it a definition, term, concept or argument, goes around in a circle so that it ends up coming full circle to where it began, just as one does when drawing a circle[i]. One way to simplistically demonstrate this symbolically is that a circular argument takes the form of: 

“P ⱡ P”[ii]

Circularity also tends to be uninformative, for instance, it doesn’t further our knowledge or provide a classification. In her second treatise, Shepherd seems to appeal to this when she claims that the Idealist position is uninformative and possibly circular if Idealism takes it to be axiomatic that knowledge only comes from perception[iii]. She points out that, conversely, if we didn’t perceive anything then we wouldn’t know anything so it doesn’t develop the argument or help explain abstract propositions[iv].

A description that I find excellently captures the core of what constitutes circularity, is the “strong condition” that it occurs when “there is a premise, either implicit or explicit, that is logically equivalent to the conclusion. That is, the premise and the conclusion must have the same truth conditions.”[v] In Shepherd’s first treatise[vi], she shows an awareness of this description of circularity:

“it is equally illogical, to prove the conclusion by the premises, and the premises by the conclusion.”[vii]

Nevertheless, “There is no simple argument form that all and only circular arguments have”[viii] so they can be notoriously difficult to spot and prove with certainty. Even one and the same argument can be circular or not depending on how one argues it. For instance:

(1)    “The article on inference contains no split infinitives.

(2)    The other articles contain no split infinitives.

Therefore,

(3)    No article contains split infinitives.”[ix]

If we assent to (1) and (2) for reasons, and perhaps evidence, that are autonomous from (3), then the argument above is not circular[x]. However, if we were to begin by implicitly (or explicitly for that matter) assuming and assenting to (3) and therefore argue for (1) and (2) to convince people of (3) as a conclusion, then we would be arguing in a circle because we would be both starting and ending with (3)[xi]. This is despite the fact that the premises (1) and (2) do not recycle the same content as the conclusion (3)[xii].

A closely related problem to circularity (although often used synonymously with circularity), but is actually somewhat distinct from it, is begging the question. A way to check this argument above to see if it begs the question is to ask oneself if not assenting to the conclusion (3) would mean we would also be rejecting the premises (1) and (2)[xiii]. Another consideration, just as with circularity, is whether we assent to (1) and (2) autonomously of (3)[xiv]. I think, although question begging and circularity, are very related to each other, they also benefit from being considered separately because a statement can be one without being the other, or commit both or neither fallacy.     

Shepherd’s preoccupation with being precise and making clear distinctions is, I argue, part of what makes Shepherd’s philosophy analytical. “A major technique of analytic philosophy is to try to formulate precisely the meanings of terms”[xv]. This is especially because, “in doing analytic philosophy, we wish to be as clear and precise as possible, we must find a way to eliminate the possibility of confusion arising from this ambiguity”[xvi]. One way of doing this is to “distinguish A and B” to avoid circularity in our definitions where A is the definiendum (that which is being defined) and B is the definiens (that which gives the meaning for the term being defined, preferably intuitively)[xvii]. The definiens helps to expose potential circularity because if the definiens is left open to misunderstanding or too broad an interpretation then it introduces vagueness which encourages a recycling of terms and concepts so potentially leading to circularity[xviii]. In this way, analytic philosophy can move beyond the often inherently circular nature of dictionary style definitions by specifying that when A means or is defined as B we are trying to express an equality between the definiendum and the definiens such that:

“A df B”[xix]

Similarly, the “technique of explication”, like definitions, also involves separating the explicandum (imprecise version of what we are trying to explain)[xx] from the explicatum (an alternative, more precise and clear version of the explicandum, as advocated by the analytic philosopher, Carnap (1891-1970))[xxi].

Although giving definitions, explanations and making use of the question and answer structure goes back centuries before Shepherd and were made famous by Aristotle, I suggest that Shepherd’s methodological approach is more in the style of contemporary approaches to analytic philosophy, even though analytic philosophy is usually seen as being founded by philosophers later on in the nineteenth century such as Frege (1848-1925), who was born after Shepherd’s death. However, I think it is plausible that Shepherd may have been the first philosopher (or at least one of the first) to combine pure philosophy with a contemporary-style analytic methodology. This is because this style already existed during Shepherd’s lifetime, albeit expressed by someone who was not a pure philosopher but rather saw himself as a theologian, logician, rhetorician, economist and social reformer, Archbishop Richard Whately. So, although Shepherd was always particularly interested by abstract thought and logic, was she somewhat influenced by Whately (1787-1863)? I think she was, given that he was part of her inner circle of friends[xxii] and he published on subjects such as logic, circularity, miracles and argued against Hume around the same time as Shepherd and seems to share a similar approach to her so they may well have exchanged ideas, benefiting from each other’s views and influence. Furthermore, it has been argued that Whately and his book ‘Elements of Logic' (1826) is closer in style to those in the latter part of the nineteenth century than those before his time[xxiii]. Furthermore, in this book, Whately briefly describes what begging the question and a circular argument is:

“The remaining kind, “petitio principii,” (begging the question,) takes place when a Premiss, whether true or false, is either plainly equivalent to the Conclusion, or depends on it for its own reception. It is to be observed, however, that in all correct Reasoning the Premises must, virtually, imply the conclusion; so that it is not possible to mark precisely the distinction between the Fallacy in question and fair argument; since that may be correct and fair Reasoning to one person, which would be, to another, begging the question, since to one the Conclusion might be more evident than the Premiss, and to the other, the reverse. The most plausible form of this Fallacy is arguing in a circle; and the greater the circle, the harder to detect.” [xxiv]  

So both Shepherd and Whately are discussing circularity and good logical, analytic argument forms around the same time as each other. However, unlike Whately, Shepherd only applies her logical, analytic approach to pure philosophy so, I suggest, she should be considered the first analytical philosopher. Whately is rather her academic peer who is revolutionising his disciplines in a similar, parallel way to the way she is revolutionising her discipline of philosophy: Whately influenced logic at Oxford[xxv] just as Shepherd influenced the Edinburgh School[xxvi]. Both also knew the Mills very well.

Thus, I pose the question that, if Whately can be considered to have a latter nineteenth century style of logic and still, all this time later, be a canonical thinker to study on topics such as analysis and logical fallacies[xxvii], then why not see Shepherd in a similar light? I suggest that Shepherd could be seen as having a later nineteenth century style of analytic philosophy (and thereby possessing this style of philosophy earlier than the commonly considered father of analytic philosophy, Frege) just as Whately can be seen as possessing a style of logic that was ahead of his time.







[i] D. H. Sanford, ‘Circular Reasoning’, ed. R. Audi, The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (USA: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p144.
[ii] E. J. Lemmon, Beginning Logic, 2nd edition (London, United Kingdom: Chapman & Hall, 1994), p34.
[iii] Shepherd, Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation, 82.
[iv] Shepherd, 82–83.
[v] Michael O’Rourke, ‘Handout: Circularity and Begging the Question’, educational, University of Idaho, USA: M. O’Rourke’s profile, summer 1999, http://www.webpages.uidaho.edu/~morourke/404-phil/Summer-99/Handouts/Philosophical/Circularity-and-Begging-the-Question.htm.
[vi] Mary Shepherd, An Essay upon the Relation of Cause and Effect : Controverting the Doctrine of Mr. Hume, Concerning the Nature of That Relation, with Observations upon the Opinions of Dr. Brown and Mr. Lawrence Connected with the Same Subject (London, United Kingdom: Printed for T. Hookham, 1824), https://archive.org/stream/essayuponrelatio00shepiala#page/n7/mode/2up.
[vii] Shepherd, 90.
[viii] Sanford, ‘Circular Reasoning’, p144.
[ix] Sanford, p144.
[x] Sanford, p144.
[xi] Sanford, 144.
[xii] Sanford, p144.
[xiii] O’Rourke, ‘Handout: Circularity and Begging the Question’.
[xiv] O’Rourke.
[xv] S. Gorovitz and R. G. Williams, Philosophical Analysis: An Introduction to Its Language & Techniques, 2nd edition (New York, USA: Random House, 1969), 101.
[xvi] Gorovitz and Williams, 103–4.
[xvii] Gorovitz and Williams, 104.
[xviii] Gorovitz and Williams, 105.
[xix] Gorovitz and Williams, 104.
[xx] Gorovitz and Williams, 105.
[xxi] Patrick Maher, ‘Lecture 2 The Methodology of Explication’, educational, Patrick Maher, Spring 2007, http://patrick.maher1.net/517/lectures/lecture2.pdf.
[xxii] Jennifer McRobert, ‘Mary Shepherd and the Causal Relation’ February 2002, p48, p52, https://philpapers.org/archive/MCRMSA.pdf.
[xxiii] J. Van Evra, ‘Richard Whately and the Rise of Modern Logic’, History and Philosophy of Logic 5, no. 1 (1984): 1–18, https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/01445348408837059.
[xxiv] Richard Whately, Logic (Elements of Logic) (London, UK: J. J. Griffin & Co., 1849), p61, https://archive.org/stream/logic00whatgoog#page/n3/mode/2up.
[xxv] O. L. Pence, ‘The Concept and Function of Logical Proof in the Rhetorical System of Richard Whately’, Speech Monographs (National Communication Association,Taylor and Francis Group) 20, no. 1 (1953): 23–28, https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1080/03637755309375076.
[xxvi] McRobert, ‘Mary Shepherd and the Causal Relation’, p5.
[xxvii] Pence, ‘The Concept and Function of Logical Proof in the Rhetorical System of Richard Whately’.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.

Shepherd vol 2 ebook: Bibliography

  Bibliography: Dictionary Scottish Architects | Part of Historic Environment Scotland. ‘25DSA Architect Biography Report in Dictionary of S...