Tuesday 23 January 2018

Shepherd vol 1 ebook chapter 7 (Plausible In Their Era?)


Chapter 7: Given Shepherd’s Objections, Do Hume’s Views On Miracles Need Adjusting To Be Plausible In Their Era?  

In this chapter, I will explore the question of whether, given Shepherd’s counterarguments[i], Hume (EHU 10) still has the resources within his argument against miracles to defend his claims as they stand or whether his concepts need re-working to remain plausible. I shall explore the plausibility of Hume’s arguments within their era, before examining present day examples of miracles and unusual, marvellous events in the next chapter, in order to assess how well Hume’s arguments function within various contexts. I would like to suggest that Hume (EHU 10) does need to adjust his definition of miracles to defend his views more successfully within his era. I think the criticism that Shepherd raises[ii] about Hume’s definition of a miracle is a problem that Hume would need to address. 

This is because I agree with Shepherd[iii] that scripture does not seem to describe a miracle in terms of a violation of natural laws occurring. Her definition does fit with scripture and with common Christian views of miracles. 

A scriptural problem with seeing miracles as a break in the laws of nature is that it implies that God only acts rarely and sporadically in the world. However, a biblical view of God’s providence is that God is constantly acting in the world, for instance, by causing rain to fall and grass to grow, and that miracles are simply more extraordinary types of events which are harder to explain. Nevertheless, in Hume’s defence, he does allow for God acting through the laws of nature (EHU 10.99 SBN 129). So he may, in this sense, cohere with the Old Testament even if his narrow definition of a miracle doesn’t. Moreover, Shepherd [iv]states that the etymological root of the word miracle is ‘wonder’. Catholics also take notice of the Latin word for miracle which I think is important because, out of the various Christian denominations, Catholicism places the greatest emphasis on miracles. So it is helpful and efficient to have a definition and account of miracles which can accommodate Catholicism into the debate.   

Another way Shepherd’s view might cohere with Catholicism is that, by seeing a miracle as being caused by God acting as an additional cause, her description may be relevant to how the Vatican has been cited as giving the definition of a miracle “as an intervention of God that goes above and beyond the laws of nature” [v]. However, Hume may have defended his definition by arguing that (EHU 10.93; SBN 117) he does not wish to use the word wonder in his definition because wonder is a passion which impairs a person’s ability to give true testimony. Hume (EHU 10.93; SBN 117) is also concerned that the passion of wonder can give rise to people assenting to beliefs, not in virtue of involving their cognitive, critical faculties, but rather because they were under the influence of, what I suggest he may see as a violent passion. I base this interpretation of Hume on wonder in part two of his Enquiry where Hume writes: 

“The passion of surprise and wonder, arising from miracles, being an agreeable emotion, gives a sensible tendency towards the belief of those events, from which it is derived” and “But if the spirit of religion join itself to the love of wonder, there is an end of common sense; and human testimony, in these circumstances, loses all pretensions to authority” (EHU 10.93; SBN 117). 

However, he is still open to the objection that, by leaving out the aspect of wonder and certainly in any positive way, he is not in line with scripture or what people understand by a miracle and may be unduly concerned about the negative effects of wonder and ignoring any potentially positive impacts of the passion of wonder.   

Furthermore, I argue that Shepherd’s perspective is neither untraditional nor detracts from the specialness of a miracle that Christians want to retain. St. Augustine and Aquinas are foundational thinkers in Christian theology and also see miracles as not going against nature. In Shepherd’s own era, her close friends concur with the view that a miracle does not break with the laws of nature. Archbishop Whately cited that: “Jesus himself accordingly ascribes his works, not as violations of the laws of nature but as “works which none other man did.”[vi] Shepherd’s statement that miracles do not break with the laws of nature also gels with the analytic thinker, inventor and mathematician Babbage who, in his chapter on miracles states: “Miracles, therefore, are not the breach of established laws, but they are the very circumstances that indicate the existence of far higher laws, which at the appointed time produce their pre-intended results.”[vii] All this, I think, adds further religious, philosophical and analytical weight and support to her argument against Hume’s definition of a miracle. 

So I would argue that Hume’s definition needs adjusting in order to fit with scripture. I suggest that he could have incorporated his aside about God acting through the laws of nature (EHU 10.99 SBN 129) into forming part of his definition of a miracle as well as making use of this concept to strengthen his arguments about nature and miracles. Also, I agree with Shepherd that his wording of the laws of nature being violated are not satisfactorily justified in terms of being in accordance with widely held views of miracles. I have shown that there is evidence that Shepherd is not alone in thinking that Hume’s definition is inadequate, unsatisfactory or, at best, incomplete because it doesn’t account for a wide enough range of categories of miracles and it also causes metaphysical, epistemological and explanatory problems for a comprehensive account of miracles. Hence, another way Hume (EHU 10) could have tried to protect his account from criticisms, such as Shepherd’s counterarguments, would be to incorporate a broader, more flexible range of possibilities concerning what a miracle constitutes and how they might occur in the world. 

In a footnote, Hume (EHU 10.90 footnote 1; SBN 115) does attempt to achieve this by providing some eye-catching examples of events to illustrate his point and widen the scope of his debate by including events which can be “discoverable by men or not”. He illustrates his point with two examples, one of an invisible miracle and one of a visible miracle (EHU 10.90 footnote 1; SBN 115). Hume claims that he would consider a feather floating in a way that goes against the laws of nature to be an instance of a miracle even if nobody perceives or reports this event (EHU 10.90 footnote 1; SBN 115). His examples of a “visible miracle” include the “raising of a house or ship into the air” (EHU 10.90 footnote 1; SBN 115). 

However, much as this discussion is a thought provoking way to explore the topic of miracles, I maintain that this short passage in his footnote (EHU 10.90 footnote 1; SBN 115) may not assist his argument for two reasons. First, by briefly including unperceived miracles, he could potentially be undermining the empirical, observation and experience-based account which details at length the problem of previously unobserved events which seem miraculous. This raises the question of how reliable an empirical approach is for detecting the existence of miracles if they may occur unperceived by humans. Second, Hume (EHU 10.90 footnote 1; SBN 115) counts a house lifting up among miracles but it could be argued in retrospect that he’s unintentionally proved Shepherd’s point about limited knowledge with such examples. This is because houses can be lifted up by a tornado. It is a very rare phenomenon but is in accordance with the laws of nature and would be repeatable under similar conditions. This means that, if Hume had known about tornados and what effects they can produce, then he would no longer count this event as a miracle. Hence, I think this provides support for and illustrates a valid concern of Shepherd’s that Hume’s approach may limit what people consider worthy of full and serious investigation thereby diminishing our knowledge of rare and apparently exceptional phenomenon which, in turn, increases our detailed knowledge of the external world.







[i] Mary Shepherd, ‘“Essay VIII: That Human Testimony Is Of Sufficient Force To Establish the Credibility Of Miracles.”’, in Essays on the Perception of an External Universe and Other Subjects Connected with the Doctrine of Causation (Piccadilly, London, United Kingdom: John hatchard and Son., 1827), 325–45, https://archive.org/stream/essaysonpercepti00shep/#page/n7/mode/2up.
[ii] Shepherd.
[iii] Shepherd.
[iv] Shepherd.
[v] Brown, ‘Did Mother Teresa Really Perform Miracles’, Telegraph Newspaper Online, 2016, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/0/did-mother-teresa-really-perform-miracles/.
[vi] Richard Whately, ‘Lesson V. Miracles. Part I.’, in Introductory Lessons on Christian Evidence, from the 12th London edition (Philadelphia: H. Hooker, S. W. Cor. Eighth and Chestnut Streets, 1856), p37-8, https://archive.org/stream/introductoryles02whatgoog#page/n42/mode/2up.
[vii] Charles Babbage, Passages from the Life of a Philosopher (London, United Kingdom: Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts & Green., 1864), p391, https://archive.org/stream/passagesfromlife03char#page/n7/mode/2up.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.

Shepherd vol 2: Bibliography

 Bibliography: